ストア派とは? わかりやすく解説

Weblio 辞書 > 辞書・百科事典 > 百科事典 > ストア派の意味・解説 

ストア派

出典: フリー百科事典『ウィキペディア(Wikipedia)』 (2024/01/05 03:34 UTC 版)

ストア派(ストアは、: Στωικισμός: Stoicism、ストイシズム)は、ヘレニズム哲学の一学派で、紀元前3世紀初めの古代ギリシャゼノンによって始められた。


  1. ^ ο θεός
  1. ^ NHK2019年4月1日放送、100分de名著「マルクス・アウレリウス」『自省録』第1回 自分の「内」を見よ。岸見一郎
  2. ^ a b Stoicism, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  3. ^ John Sellars. Stoicism, p. 32.
  4. ^ a b Agathias. Histories, 2.31.
  5. ^ a b David, Sedley (1998). "Ancient philosophy". In E. Craig (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008年10月18日閲覧
  6. ^ a b Gnuse, Robert Karl (1 May 1997). No Other Gods: Emergent Monotheism in Israel. Sheffield Academic Press. p. 225. ISBN 1-85075-657-0. https://books.google.com/books?id=pBSJNDndGjwC&pg=PA225 
  7. ^ a b c d Brenk, Frederick (January 2016). “Pagan Monotheism and Pagan Cult”. "Theism" and Related Categories in the Study of Ancient Religions. SCS/AIA Annual Meeting. 75.4. Philadelphia: Society for Classical Studies (University of Pennsylvania). オリジナルの6 May 2017時点におけるアーカイブ。. https://classicalstudies.org/annual-meeting/147/abstract/pagan-monotheism-and-pagan-cult 2021年8月3日閲覧. "Historical authors generally refer to “the divine” (to theion) or “the supernatural” (to daimonion) rather than simply “God.” [...] The Stoics, believed in a God identifiable with the logos or hegemonikon (reason or leading principle) of the universe and downgraded the traditional gods, who even disappear during the conflagration (ekpyrosis). Yet, the Stoics apparently did not practice a cult to this God. Middle and Later Platonists, who spoke of a supreme God, in philosophical discourse, generally speak of this God, not the gods, as responsible for the creation and providence of the universe. They, too, however, do not seem to have directly practiced a religious cult to their God." 
  8. ^ Epictetus, Discourses 1.15.2, Robin Hard revised translation.
  9. ^ a b Russell, Bertrand. A History of Western Philosophy, p. 254.
  10. ^ a b Russell, Bertrand. A History of Western Philosophy, p. 264.
  11. ^ Russell, Bertrand. A History of Western Philosophy, p. 253.
  12. ^ Charles Hartshorne and William Reese, "Philosophers Speak of God," Humanity Books, 1953 ch 4
  13. ^ Amos, H. (1982). These Were the Greeks. Chester Springs: Dufour Editions. ISBN 978-0-8023-1275-4. OCLC 9048254 
  14. ^ Gilbert Murray, The Stoic Philosophy (1915), p.25. In Bertrand Russell, A History of Western Philosophy (1946).
  15. ^ Becker, Lawrence (2003). A History of Western Ethics. New York: Routledge. p. 27. ISBN 978-0-415-96825-6 
  16. ^ A.A.Long, Hellenistic Philosophy, p.115.
  17. ^ [1] Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Susanne Bobzien, Ancient Logic
  18. ^ [2] Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Susanne Bobzien, Ancient Logic
  19. ^ Diogenes Laërtius (2000). Lives of eminent philosophers. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press  VII.49
  20. ^ Seneca, Epistles, lxv. 2.
  21. ^ Marcus Aurelius, Meditations, iv. 21.
  22. ^ Zeller 1931, p. 274.
  23. ^ Pagan Monotheism in Late Antiquity, Edited by Polymnia Athanassiadi, Michael Frede, CLARENDON PRESS • OXFORD(1999), p. 8. "One way of justifying to themselves and to others their attachment to specific gods was to proclaim that what was really being worshipped under various names and historically sanctioned forms of cult was the one ineffable principle of all things. Unambiguously professed in a sentence like the following: ‘God being one, has many names’,12 this belief permeates Greek religious theory. The Stoic Cleanthes can thus address a fervent hymn to Zeus as a god with a definite historical personality, in which we encounter a monistic view of divinity.13 Indeed this may be the reason why this pagan prayer was selected by Stobaeus, along with a similar Orphic hymn to Zeus, for the anthology that he compiled for his son’s use and education"
  24. ^ Pagan Monotheism in Late Antiquity, Edited by Polymnia Athanassiadi, Michael Frede, CLARENDON PRESS • OXFORD(1999), p. 19. "Platonists and Aristotelians defined God as absolutely immaterial and therefore transcending the world of the senses, while the Stoics taught that, though incorporeal, God displays a form of materiality, but of a very subtle and literally ethereal nature, and likened him to intelligible light or fire. Yet, as is argued in the second chapter of this volume, both had a monotheistic view, and the Christians, who drew on Greek philosophy for the formulation of their own theology, recognized this. Of the two views on offer orthodox Christianity opted for the first, without however being able to reject the Stoic position altogether, as Tertullian’s rhetorical question testifies: ‘for who will deny that God is a body, though he is a spirit?’48 This ambiguity is even more clearly present in pagan theological literature, which combines belief in a transcendental God with the worship of the Sun seen as the representation of God in this world."
  25. ^ a b Pagan Monotheism in Late Antiquity, Edited by Polymnia Athanassiadi, Michael Frede, CLARENDON PRESS • OXFORD(1999), pp. 43-44. "the Platonists, the Peripatetics, and the Stoics do not just believe in one highest god, they believe in something which they must take to be unique even as a god. For they call it ‘God’ or even ‘the God’, as if in some crucial way it was the only thing which deserved to be called ‘god’. If, thus, they also believe that there are further beings which can be called ‘divine’ or ‘god’, they must have thought that these further beings could be called ‘divine’ only in some less strict, diminished, or derived sense. Second, the Christians themselves speak not only of the one true God, but also of a plurality of beings which can be called ‘divine’ or ‘god’; for instance, the un-fallen angels or redeemed and saved human beings."
  26. ^ Pagan Monotheism in Late Antiquity, Edited by Polymnia Athanassiadi, Michael Frede, CLARENDON PRESS • OXFORD(1999), p. 53. "Nevertheless, this clearly means that only Zeus satisfies the criterion for being a god fully, whereas all other gods only satisfy the criterion by not insisting on strict indestructibility, but by accepting a weak form of immortality. It is only in this diminished sense that things other than Zeus can be called ‘god’. More importantly, though, these other gods only exist because the God has created them as part of his creation of the best possible world, in which they are meant to play a certain role. The power they thus have is merely the power to do what the God has fated them to do. They act completely in accordance with the divine plan......It is very clear in their case, even more so than in Aristotle’s, that these further divine beings are radically dependent on the God and only exist because they have a place in the divine order of things. Far from governing the universe or having any independent share in its governance, they only share in the execution of the divine plan; they are not even immortal, strictly speaking. Theirs is a rather tenuous divinity."
  27. ^ Pagan Monotheism in Late Antiquity, Edited by Polymnia Athanassiadi, Michael Frede, CLARENDON PRESS • OXFORD(1999), p. 51. "But the Stoics not only think that all beings are material or corporeal, they also, more specifically, identify God or Zeus with a certain kind of fire which is supposed to be intelligent, active, and creative. So perhaps we have to assume that the Stoics distinguish two aspects of the fiery substance which is Zeus, two aspects, though, which in reality are never separated, namely its divine, creative character, and its material character. Thus God and Zeus are the same to the extent that Zeus is active, creative, intelligent. Now the Stoics also believe that the world is a rational animal that periodically turns entirely into the fiery substance which is Zeus. What happens is that the reason of this animal is itself constituted by this fiery substance, and that this reason slowly consumes and absorbs into itself the soul and the body of the world. Thus, in this state of conflagration, the world, the reason of the world, and Zeus completely coincide."
  28. ^ Passion”. Merriam-Webster. Encyclopædia Britannica. 2011年1月29日閲覧。
  29. ^ Graver, Margaret (2009). Stoicism and Emotion. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-30558-5. OCLC 430497127 
  30. ^ Seddon, Keith (2005). Epictetus' Handbook and the Tablet of Cebes. New York: Routledge. p. 217. ISBN 978-0-415-32451-9. OCLC 469313282 
  31. ^ a b Don E. Marietta, (1998), Introduction to ancient philosophy, pages 153-4. Sharpe
  32. ^ "Cato's suicide in Plutarch AV Zadorojnyi" (Document). The Classical Quarterly. 2007 {{cite document}}: 不明な引数|url=は無視されます。 (説明)
  33. ^ William Braxton Irvine, (2009), A guide to the good life: the ancient art of Stoic joy, Oxford University Press, p. 200.
  34. ^ Davidson, A.I. (1995) Pierre Hadot and the Spiritual Phenomenon of Ancient Philosophy, in Philosophy as a Way of Life, Hadot, P. Oxford Blackwells pp. 9-10.
  35. ^ Hadot, P. (1992) La Citadelle intérieure. Introduction aux Pensées de Marc Aurèle. Paris, Fayard, pp. 106-115.
  36. ^ Hadot, P (1987) Exercices spirituels et philosophie antique. Paris, 2nd edn, p. 135.
  37. ^ Mac Suibhne, S. (2009). “'Wrestle to be the man philosophy wished to make you': Marcus Aurelius, reflective practitioner”. Reflective Practice 10 (4): 429–436. doi:10.1080/14623940903138266. 
  38. ^ Robertson, D (2010). The Philosophy of Cognitive-Behavioral Therapy: Stoicism as Rational and Cognitive Psychotherapy. London: Karnac. ISBN 978-1-85575-756-1. https://books.google.co.uk/books?id=XsOFyJaR5vEC&lpg=&hl=en 
  39. ^ Epictetus, Discourses, ii. 5. 26
  40. ^ Epictetus, Discourses, i. 9. 1
  41. ^ Seneca, Moral letters to Lucilius, Letter 47: On master and slave, 10, circa 65 AD.
  42. ^ On the Duties of the Clergy”. www.newadvent.org. 2017年3月1日閲覧。
  43. ^ Aurelius, Marcus (1964). Meditations. London: Penguin Books. p. 26. ISBN 978-0-140-44140-6. https://archive.org/details/meditations0000marc_m9z0 
  44. ^ a b Marcus Aurelius (1964). Meditations. London: Penguin Books. p. 25. ISBN 978-0-140-44140-6. https://archive.org/details/meditations0000marc_m9z0 
  45. ^ a b c Ferguson, Everett. Backgrounds of Early Christianity. 2003, page 368.
  46. ^ Grafton, Anthony; Most, Glenn W.; Settis, Salvatore (2010-10-25) (英語). The Classical Tradition. Harvard University Press. p. 911. ISBN 978-0-674-03572-0. https://books.google.co.uk/books?id=LbqF8z2bq3sC&pg=PA911 
  47. ^ 森本あんり『現代に語りかけるキリスト教』日本キリスト教団出版局、1998年、79頁。ISBN 9784818403307 
  48. ^ 森本あんり『現代に語りかけるキリスト教』日本キリスト教団出版局、1998年、81頁。ISBN 9784818403307 
  49. ^ Harper, Douglas (2001年11月). “Online Etymology Dictionary — Stoic”. 2006年9月2日閲覧。
  50. ^ Baltzly, Dirk (2004年12月13日). “Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy — Stoicism”. 2006年9月2日閲覧。




このページでは「ウィキペディア」からストア派を検索した結果を表示しています。
Weblioに収録されているすべての辞書からストア派を検索する場合は、下記のリンクをクリックしてください。
 全ての辞書からストア派を検索

英和和英テキスト翻訳>> Weblio翻訳
英語⇒日本語日本語⇒英語
  

辞書ショートカット

すべての辞書の索引

「ストア派」の関連用語

ストア派のお隣キーワード
検索ランキング

   

英語⇒日本語
日本語⇒英語
   



ストア派のページの著作権
Weblio 辞書 情報提供元は 参加元一覧 にて確認できます。

   
ウィキペディアウィキペディア
All text is available under the terms of the GNU Free Documentation License.
この記事は、ウィキペディアのストア派 (改訂履歴)の記事を複製、再配布したものにあたり、GNU Free Documentation Licenseというライセンスの下で提供されています。 Weblio辞書に掲載されているウィキペディアの記事も、全てGNU Free Documentation Licenseの元に提供されております。

©2024 GRAS Group, Inc.RSS